Sobre la virtuosidad de ciertas negativas a cumplir con exigencias legales motivadas por otras normatividades

Autores/as

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.5294/dika.2023.32.1.22

Palabras clave:

Ética de la virtud, desobediencia civil, fenomenología, ley natural, filosofía del derecho

Resumen

En este artículo se analiza la forma en que la ética de la virtud, con su consideración del contexto en el que deben comportarse los agentes morales, puede arrojar luz sobre las circunstancias bajo las cuales una decisión deliberada de incumplir un determinado mandato legal puede considerarse no solo como permisible desde lo moral sino incluso como la forma más ética de comportarse. En esta determinación intervienen condiciones sustantivas de “no hacer daño” y de debida diligencia. Además, se examina cómo la decisión de desafiar un mandato legal con plena conciencia no implica una negación de la normatividad, sino que a veces puede presuponer una voluntad de cumplir con una normatividad que el agente moral considera más prioritaria que la legal. Por ende, los factores existenciales y emocionales pueden configurar esta determinación.

Descargas

Los datos de descargas todavía no están disponibles.

Citas

Amartya Sen, “Elements of a Theory of Human Rights,” in Philosophy & Public Affairs, 32 (2004). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2004.00017.x

Amia Srinivasan, “Does anyone have the right to sex?” London Review of Books, 40 (2018).

Andrea Bianchi, International Law Theories, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2016.

Aristotle, Politics, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 2013.

Aristotle, The Nicomachean Ethics.

Benedict Kingsbury, “The Concept of ‘Law’ in Global Administrative Law,” in European Journal of International Law, 20 (2009). DOI: https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1397308

Brian H. Bix, “Radbruch’s Formula and Conceptual Analysis,” in The American Journal of Jurisprudence, 56 (2011). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/ajj/56.1.45

Candice Delmas and Kimberley Brownlee, “Civil Disobedience,” in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2021).

Christoph Horn, “Law, governance, and political obligation,” in Marguerite Deslauriers and Pierre Destrée (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Politics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2013.

Daniel Came, “The Themes of Affirmation and Illusion in The Birth of Tragedy and Beyond,” in John Richardson and Ken Gemes (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Nietzsche, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199534647.013.0010

Derek Parfitt, On What Matters, Volume one, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:osobl/9780199572809.001.0001

Dietrich Von Hildebrand, Humility: Wellspring of Virtue, Nashua, Sophia Institute Press, 1997.

European Court of Human Rights, Practical Guide on Admissibility Criteria, 31 August 2002 updated version.

Frédéric Gros, Désobéir, Paris, Albin Michel, 2017.

G. Alex Sinha, “Virtuous Law-Breaking,” in Washington University Jurisprudence Review, 13 (2021). DOI: https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.3682170

H. D. Lewis, “Obedience to Conscience,” in Mind, 54 (1945). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/LIV.215.227

Hannah Arendt, Crises of the Republic, New York, Harvest, 1972.

Hans Kelsen, Teoría pura del derecho, Mexico City, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, 1982.

Hans Kelsen, What is Justice? Justice, Law, and Politics in the Mirror of Science, Collected Essays, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1971.

Harold Hongju Koh, “Why Do Nations Obey International Law,” in The Yale Law Journal, 106 (1997). DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/797228

Harry Prosch, “Limits to the Moral Claim in Civil Disobedience,” in Ethics, 75 (1965). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1086/291530

Harry Prosch, “Toward an Ethics of Civil Disobedience,” in Ethics, 77 (1967). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1086/291631

Heidi M. Hurd, “The Morality of Judicial Disobedience,” in Penn Law Journal, XXIX (1993).

Heikki Matila, Comparative Legal Linguistics, Aldershot, Ashgate, 2006.

Henry David Thoreau, On the Duty of Civil Disobedience, 1849.

Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511809590

Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, Observaciones y recomendaciones de la visita de trabajo de la CIDH a Colombia realizada del 8 al 10 de junio de 2021, 2021.

Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, Press Release No. 137/21.

Inter-American Court of Human Rights, Suárez Rosero Vs. Ecuador, Judgment (Merits), 12 November 1997.

Jacob T. Levy, “Lon Fuller, The Morality of Law,” Oxford Handbooks Online.

Javier Hervada, Introducción crítica al Derecho Natural, Bogotá, Temis, 2000.

John Finnis, Natural Law & Natural Rights, 2nd edition, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2011.

John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, revised edition, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1999. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4159/9780674042582

John T. Pardun, “Good Samaritan Laws: A Global Perspective,” in Loyola of Los Angeles International and Comparative Law Review, 20 (1998).

Julie Fraser and Brianne McGonigle Leyth (eds.), Intersections of Law and Culture at the International Criminal Court, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar Publishing, 2020. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4337/9781839107306.00007

Khaled About El Fadl, “The Islamic Legal Tradition,” in Mauro Bussani and Ugo Mattei (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Comparative Law, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2013.

Kimberley Brownlee, The Moral Status of Civil Disobedience (Doctor of Philosophy Thesis), Oxford, University of Oxford, 2006.

Leon Tolstoy, What is Art? 1904, translation by Aylmer Maude.

Leslie Green, The Authority of the State, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1988.

Martha Nussbaum, Not for Profit: Why Democracy Needs The Humanities, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 2010.

Martha C. Nussbaum, Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 2013. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctt6wpqm7

Matthew Ratcliffe, “Why Mood Matters,” in Mark A. Wrathall (ed.), Heidegger’s Being and Time, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2013. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/CCO9781139047289.008

N. P. Swarts, “Thomas Aquinas: On Law, Tyranny and Resistance,” in Acta Theologica, 30 (2010). https://doi.org/10.4314/actat.v30i1.67257

Nancy Potter, The virtue of defiance and psychiatric engagement, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2016. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/med/9780199663866.003.0006

Nicolás Carrillo-Santarelli, Direct International Human Rights Obligations of Non-State Actors: A Legal and Ethical Necessity, Oisterwijk, Wolf Legal Publishers, 2017.

Nomy Arpaly, “Huckleberry Finn Revisited: Inverse Akrasia and Moral Ignorance,” in Randolph Clarke et al. (eds.), The Nature of Moral Responsibility: New Essays, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2015. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199998074.003.0007

Oliver Sensen, “Human dignity in historical perspective: The contemporary and traditional paradigms,” in European Journal of Political Theory, 10 (2011). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885110386006

Owen Ware, “Kant on Moral Sensibility and Moral Motivation,” in Journal of the History of Philosophy, 52 (2014). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2014.0090

Paolo G. Carozza, “Subsidiarity as a Structural Principle of International Human Rights Law,” in American Journal of International Law, 97 (2003). DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/3087103

Patrick Durning, “Political Legitimacy and the Duty to Obey the Law,” in Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 33 (2003). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2003.10716548

Philippa Foot, “Morality as a System of Hypothetical Imperatives,” in The Philosophical Review, 81 (1972). DOI: https://doi.org/10.2307/2184328

Piero Moraro, Civil Disobedience and Civic Virtues (Doctor of Philosophy Thesis), Stirling, University of Stirling, 2010. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/0803706X.2010.550316

Pontifical Council for Justice and Peace, Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church, Vatican City, Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 2004.

Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court.

Rosalyn Higgins, Problems & Process: International Law and How We Use It, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2004.

Scott J. Shapiro, Legality, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 2011.

Scott M. Campbell, The early Heidegger’s philosophy of life: facticity, being, and language, New York, Fordham University Press, 2012. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5422/fordham/9780823242191.001.0001

Siegfried Zepf, “About rationalization and intellectualization,” in International Forum of Psychoanalysis, 20 (2011). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/0803706X.2010.550316

Sophocles, Antigone.

Steven Crowell, “Sorge or Selbstbewußtsein? Heidegger and Korsgaard on the Sources of Normativity,” in European Journal of Philosophy, 15 (2007). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0378.2007.00267.x

T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1998.

Ted Clayton, “Political Philosophy of Alasdair MacIntyre,” in IEP.

Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, 1651.

United Nations, Principles of International Law Recognized in the Charter of the Nürnberg Tribunal and in the Judgment of the Tribunal.

Viktor E. Frankl, Man’s Search for Meaning: An Introduction to Logotherapy, 4th ed., Boston, Beacon Press, 1992.

Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, 1993.

Publicado

2023-11-21

Cómo citar

Carrillo-Santarelli, N. (2023). Sobre la virtuosidad de ciertas negativas a cumplir con exigencias legales motivadas por otras normatividades. Díkaion, 32(1), e32122. https://doi.org/10.5294/dika.2023.32.1.22

Número

Sección

Artículos